Bad cases making bad law: how the politics of denaturalising bad guys created second class citizens
How did we end up in a situation where people born British can be stripped of their citizenship? And how can we change that?
Stripping a British citizen of their status had become virtually unknown until the turn of the millennium. Since then, following a handful of actual or attempted denaturalisations in the 2000s, the practice has become commonplace. Since 2010 there have been over two hundred cases.
The evolution over the last twenty years of British law on denaturalisation — or citizenship stripping — is a case study in bad cases making bad law. The law was changed repeatedly between 2002 and 2006 specifically to enable the government to strip the citizenship of particular high profile individuals. Relatively restrained use was initially made of these new powers, with only those high profile individuals targeted for denaturalisation. A change in government in 2010 introduced changed attitudes to the value and meaning of citizenship. The new government found itself in possession of very considerable discretionary powers and set about making extensive use of them.
It is time for a reset. A new British Citizenship Act would offer an opportunity to reconsider the current approach.
Is citizenship stripping problematic?
Justifications for citizenship stripping
There are broadly three arguments publicly advanced in favour of citizenship deprivation.
One is that it is an expression of opprobrium. To deprive a person of their citizenship on the grounds of their behaviour or opinion is to cast them out of society. It can be conceptualised as a form of civic death or as a power of exile or banishment.
The second argument is a pragmatic one based on security. To exile or prevent re-entry of a dangerous individual improves public safety and security. It is only really this second argument we hear articulated by the politicians responsible for the decisions, as we will see.
There is an implicit third argument which is never — or at least seldom — spoken: that some British citizens do not really belong in the first place. They aren’t really “British” other than as a matter of legal formality. It is unproblematic to strip them of their formal legal status because they were never part of the community of belonging in the first place. This thinking surely underpins all denaturalisation decisions. The danger of a discriminatory, racialised approach to who is and is not really “British” is very high indeed.
Arguments against citizenship stripping
There are, I think, also three broad arguments against citizenship deprivation.
The first is both principled and yet also not absolute: that citizenship should only be stripped in extreme cases because citizenship is a critically important right. It should be a secure or ‘sticky’ form of status and therefore hard for a state to remove.
Currently, this is clearly not the case. In legal terms, the wording of the test for citizenship deprivation is identical to that for simple deportation: taking away a person’s citizenship merely must be, in the opinion of the Home Secretary, ‘conducive to the public good’.
The second argument is one of international solidarity: that it is generally wrong to strip a person’s citizenship and thereby foist them upon some other country to which they might have a much weaker connection than ours. It might well be in our own country that the person was radicalised. Our country should therefore be responsible.
In Shamima Begum’s case, why should Bangladesh, a country the UK asserts she is a national of, be forced to admit her when she was not born there, has never visited and has no real connection other than through her parents? She was born in the UK and grew up in the UK; is she not therefore the UK’s responsibility? Or, if she is forced to stay in Syria, why should Syria or rebel forces in Syria be responsible for her?
It is not just Shamima Begum. In the Supreme Court case of Pham v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2015] UKSC 19, for example, why should Vietnam, a country Mr Pham left aged 6, be forced to accept back a citizen who grew up and was radicalised in the United Kingdom?
The third argument is an indirect, structural one. International law forbids governments from rendering a person stateless through a citizenship deprivation based on national security. This means that citizenship may only be stripped from a person who has another nationality. Where a person only holds British citizenship, the British state therefore cannot take it away.
In some scenarios, this might make some sense. Where a person comes to the UK as an adult, naturalises as British, retains their original nationality, becomes a severe security threat, is stripped of their British citizenship and returned to their country of origin, denaturalisation might be seen as unobjectionable.
But since 2002, citizenship stripping laws apply even to those born in the United Kingdom as British citizens from birth. If they inherit a nationality from one or both their parents according to the nationality law of another state, this makes them vulnerable to having their British citizenship stripped from them. The effect can be seen in the Shamima Begum case. She was born British. Without ever going to Bangladesh, without ever having applied for a Bangladeshi passport and potentially without even knowing she was Bangladeshi, she could be stripped of her British citizenship because of who her parents were and where they came from.
Two classes of British citizen have therefore been created. British citizens born in the UK who have no immediate foreign parentage are immune from denaturalisation. They have secure status and belonging. British citizens born in the UK but with foreign parentage that means they have knowingly or unknowingly, willingly or unwillingly, inherited another nationality can be denaturalised. They have insecure status and belonging.
At the time, this change was justified on the ground that it eliminated discrimination between those born British and those naturalised as British. It ended up substituting a different form of discrimination based instead on parentage. Besides, it might well be argued that there is a qualitative difference between deprivation of a status involuntarily or voluntarily entered into.
To sum up, the functions of expressing opprobrium and protecting security can only be performed on British citizens with foreign parentage and not on others. The test for stripping a person of their citizenship is low, which might be useful from a security perspective but also means that people can potentially be stripped of their citizenship for relatively minor or ordinary criminal conduct that falls far short of, for example, threatening the security of the state. As we will see, this has now started to happen in practice. Further, British law enables the effective exile of those who are socially and culturally British with the effect that some other country to which they have no substantive connection must take responsibility for them.
Almost everyone is dissatisfied with this state of affairs. How did we get here? And what can we do about it now?
Abu Hamza
The power to denaturalise a British subject on the basis of their behaviour was first introduced by legislation in 1918. With some adjustments, the power remained broadly the same until as late as 2002. Essentially, only a person who had naturalised as British could be stripped of their citizenship and the main grounds for doing so involved disloyalty or disaffection to the Crown, assisting an enemy or proven criminal conduct. These powers were exercised against some German and allied nationals who had naturalised as British but fell into abeyance. The last denaturalisation under this legal regime occurred in 1973.
After 80 years of legal continuity, a period which included a second world war, the Cold War and The Troubles, amongst other external-internal existential security threats, a series of fundamental changes to the law on denaturalisation began in 2002. Why?
In 2002, reforms for the first time enabled denaturalisation of those born as British citizens, as long as they were not thus rendered stateless, and introduced a new test of doing anything ‘seriously prejudicial to the vital interests of the United Kingdom’. Both of these changes represented genuinely radical changes to the law.
These reforms were presaged by a White Paper, albeit only in scant outline, and appeared in the original draft legislation that was presented to Parliament. The new test for denaturalisation was derived from international conventions on statelessness and nationality. The changes look like they were considered relatively thoroughly in advance, at least in comparison to later changes.
But just three days after the new powers came into effect, the notorious cleric Abu Hamza was served with a notice of intention to strip him of his British citizenship. He was possibly the only, if not then one of the only, British citizens targeted for denaturalisation under this new but short-lived legal regime. Were the changes actually all about getting rid of Hamza?
Hamza held Egyptian citizenship and had naturalised as British, making him a dual national. He could therefore potentially be removed to Egypt and was potentially subject to denaturalisation under the old legal regime. However, he had been convicted of no offences and disloyalty or disaffection might well have been considered too ephemeral a mental state to use as a basis for such a draconian and controversial act.
It is plausible to suggest that the 2002 reform was conceived specifically to target Hamza. He was certainly in the public eye from at least 2001 onwards. Shortly before the reform came into effect, then Home Secretary David Blunkett stated, referring specifically to Hamza, that ‘every word and every action is being monitored, and we need to do so in a way that secures the confidence of people who are sick and tired of individuals like him abusing our hospitality.’
Without doubt, the change certainly enabled his denaturalisation and it was intended for use against other perceived supporters of radical political Islam.
Abu Hamza Again
However, there is an important post script. Denaturalisation did not take immediate effect because Hamza appealed and the law provided that his status was protected until the conclusion of the appeal. While the appeal was ongoing, the Egyptian government then stripped Hamza of his Egyptian citizenship. This meant that the only nationality held by Hamza was his British citizenship. He could therefore no longer be denaturalised by the British government, because to do so would render him stateless. His appeal succeeded and Abu Hamza remains a British citizen to this day.
As Audrey Macklin has put it, there is a ‘race to see which country can strip citizenship first. To the loser goes the citizen’. The British government, eager to avoid losing any similar races in future, changed the law again in 2004.
The legal provision continuing citizenship during any appeal was quietly repealed by a new piece of legislation not otherwise addressing nationality law at all: paragraph 4 of Schedule 2 of the ill-named Asylum and Immigration (Treatment of Claimants, etc) Act 2004. A person’s citizenship would be immediately withdrawn on receipt of a decision, irrespective of whether the person pursued an appeal or not. If the appeal were to succeed, the person’s citizenship would be restored.
The change had a significant side-effect. If a British citizen was denaturalised while outside the country, this meant they would be unable to return, even to contest any appeal they might lodge. It would also become harder to resource and contest any appeal, or even to get an appeal lodged in the first place given the strict and inflexible time limits imposed. In a process led by the security services, denaturalisation decisions were henceforth served as soon as a person was outside the country, in effect exiling the recipients.
However, the old law would continue to apply to past events and actions; it was only matters arising after the commencement of the new test to which the new test would apply. This was to become relevant to the next ‘bad guy’.
David Hicks
Further legal changes were wrought to the law of denaturalisation in 2006. The ‘seriously prejudicial to the vital interests of the United Kingdom’ test was replaced with one of merely whether denaturalisation was considered by the Home Secretary to be ‘conducive to the public good’.
The new test was on the face of it unrelated to issues of state-level or civic harm or questions of loyalty. The threshold of conduct was potentially far lower and it was far harder to challenge in court. Indeed, the new test for denaturalisation used identical wording to the test for deporting foreign nationals on the basis of criminal or merely undesirable behaviour. It is an incredibly low bar for taking away a person’s citizenship.
Unlike the reforms of 2002 and 2004, though, this change was not seemingly one that was pre-planned. There was no White Paper and the original Bill presented to Parliament on 22 June 2005 was silent on the issue of citizenship deprivation. The relevant clause was only introduced by the government at the scrutiny stage of the legislative process, in October 2005.
The minister responsible, Tony McNulty, claimed that the purpose was to enable denaturalisation in the event that British citizen engaged in ‘certain unacceptable behaviours’ in breach of the government’s ‘wider counter-terrorism initiative’. Admitting that the existing powers introduced in 2002 had not led to any actual denaturalisations (although notably silent on the failed attempt to denaturalise Abu Hamza), McNulty justified the change by asserting
‘[w]e think that things have moved on and it is appropriate to have the power that we are discussing in the locker, if nothing else, given the way circumstances are.’
Pausing here, that was a truly remarkable thing to say.
Past behaviour by a British citizen would not be the only factor in denaturalisation decisions under the new test. Ministers would also consider ‘potential threat’ and ‘a particular threat now from which the public need protection’. Finally, the minister all but admitted that the changes were not compatible with the international treaties from which the ‘seriously prejudicial’ test had been drawn.
A seemingly unrelated amendment was introduced at the same time, which imposed for the first time the good character test on registrations as British nationals.
The saga of eligibility for British citizenship of David Hicks was running in parallel with these developments. Hicks was an Australian citizen who had ended up detained by the United States government at Guantanamo Bay on suspicion of involvement with Islamist terrorist groups prior to his capture in Afghanistan in 2001. He reportedly became aware he was eligible for registration as a British citizen in September 2005 and submitted an application soon afterwards in the hope this might prompt his release from detention.
The application was rejected by the Home Office in November 2005. Eventually, after a series of court defeats for the British government, Hicks was briefly to be registered as British. Because the ‘seriously prejudicial’ test only applied to events after it came into force in 2003, it was actually the original test for citizenship deprivation set out in the 1981 legislation that was considered by the courts in Hicks’ case. The Court of Appeal held that Hicks could have shown neither disloyalty nor disaffection because both require ‘an attitude of mind towards an entity to which allegiance is owed, or at least to which the person belongs or is attached.’ He had not been British at the time so had owed no allegiance.
In the meantime, the British government introduced the two amendments discussed above to the Bill then passing through Parliament. These amendments would have empowered the government to refuse Hicks’ registration on good character grounds and, because this came too late, also enabled the government to denaturalise Hicks as soon as his registration had eventually been granted in July 2006.
Two major changes to British nationality law were seemingly driven by one man. The lowering of the bar for citizenship stripping would affect hundreds of British citizens. The imposition of a good character test for registrations would go on to affect thousands.
Al Jedda
The correlation between legal change and individual cases does not end there. In 2014, the law was changed so that a British citizen could be in some circumstances be denaturalised even if this rendered them stateless.
Once again, the relevant clause was not included in the Bill originally presented to Parliament. It was only after the handing down of the Supreme Court decision in Al Jedda v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2013] UKSC 62 that the Bill was amended to include this provision. The accompanying explanatory notes accompanying the amendment made the link absolutely explicit, specifically citing the Al Jedda case. The government minister presenting the amendment in the House of Lords was more circumspect, arguing the new power was needed ‘to allow a small number of naturalised citizens who have taken up arms against British forces overseas or acted in some other manner seriously prejudicial to the vital interests of the UK to be deprived of their citizenship, regardless of whether it leaves them stateless.’
D4
The pattern was repeated in the parliamentary session of 2021-22. The Nationality and Borders Bill initially introduced to Parliament on 6 July 2021 did not touch on denaturalisation. On 30 July 2021, the High Court held that notice had to be given in writing in order for a denaturalisation decision to take effect in a case called R (On the Application Of D4) v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2021] EWHC 2179 (Admin) (later confirmed by the Court of Appeal).
It did not take the government long to respond. An amendment was introduced at the committee stage in November 2021 to abolish this requirement.
Unintended consequences: the slippery slope
These developments follow a classic pattern in immigration law. Legislative constraints are imposed when a draconian course of action is considered hypothetical. This is done to reassure parliamentarians and civil society in order to minimise opposition to the power in question and ensure smooth passage of the legislation. When a real world case finally arises and officials and ministers find their freedom of action constrained, they quickly dispose of those constraints. In parallel, procedural rights for individuals are conferred when they are abstract. As soon as they are needed they are abolished.
The governments and ministers who introduced the initial changes to the law between 2002 and 2006 were relatively restrained in making use of them. The numbers of denaturalisations remained very low until 2010, when there was a change of government and a change of approach. For the incoming government, citizenship was a privilege not a right. A privilege is revocable. A right is not.
The problem is that when very low legal thresholds for draconian actions are introduced, ministers and civil servants are handed huge freedom of action. Particularly in the field of immigration and asylum law, they are subject to huge political and media pressures. It should be no surprise if they are inconsistent in their use of the very considerable powers with which they have been entrusted by an earlier parliament. It should also be no surprise that unconscious bias asserts itself in these circumstances.
Behaviour-base denaturalisations peaked in 2017 at around the time that the territorial area in Iraq and Syria controlled by the ISIS or Islamic State group was collapsing. British citizens who had associated with the group were looking to escape and return home. The Home Secretary at the time was Amber Rudd, but it is her successor, Sajid Javid, who has provided the most detailed public justification for denaturalisation action.
Speaking on breakfast television about Shamima Begum in 2021, several years after his time as Home Secretary, he claimed that
‘[i]f you did know what I knew, as I say because you are sensible, responsible people, you would have made exactly the same decision, of that I have no doubt.’
Javid retrospectively framed the decision as one involving risk to the British public, essentially.
He has also, however, stated a very different justification for denaturalisation. At a party conference speech in 2018, when he was still Home Secretary, he boasted of expanding use of citizenship deprivation powers to ‘those who are convicted of the most grave criminal offences. This applies to some of the despicable men involved in gang-based child sexual exploitation.’ There is a clear moral dimension to this statement.
A few months later, also in 2018, he discussed the denaturalisation of a group of dual national Pakistani-British men convicted of sexual offences. Pressed on the risk to citizens of Pakistan once they were removed there, Javid he reverted to suggesting it was all a matter of risk, albeit only of risk to the British public:
‘[m]y job is to protect the British public and to do what I think is right to protect the British public.’
The protection of the Bangladeshi or Syrian public is clearly beyond his concern.
More recently, lawyers have reported that denaturalisation action is now being pursued against individuals convicted of human trafficking offences. It is hard to see how removing a person to a country from which they have previously trafficked others reduces risk to either the citizens of that country or the United Kingdom.
The expansion in the use of denaturalisation powers from threats to national security to very serious crimes would have been impossible without the reforms to citizenship deprivation law enacted in 2006 in response to the case of David Hicks. It is not realistically possible to argue that serious sexual offences or human trafficking amount to acts seriously prejudicial to the vital interests of the United Kingdom. It clearly is possible successfully to argue that such conduct is sufficient for the Home Secretary to be satisfied that denaturalisation is conducive to the public good. After all, the Rochdale sex offenders lost their legal challenge: Aziz & Ors v Secretary of State for the Home Department [2018] EWCA Civ 1884.
The fact that every known case of behaviour-based denaturalisation involves a Muslim has not gone without comment. There has undoubtedly been a serious threat to public safety from some individuals who are Muslim but it would be entirely unrealistic to suggest that the threat is uniquely posed by Muslims. Denaturalisation has never been pursued against Irish nationalists, adherents of right-wing terror groups, anarchists or other dual foreign nationals representing a threat to national security. It is possible that no such individuals were identified who held dual citizenship and were thus eligible for denaturalisation but this seems inherently unlikely.
The discrimination becomes even more stark when the case of the Rochdale sex offenders is considered. The men who were denaturalised were all Muslim men of Pakistani origin. It seems highly likely there have been many, many other dual nationals who committed sexual and other offences of similar or worse gravity — where seriousness is measured by the length of sentence rather than media judgment — who were never considered for denaturalisation.
The changes made to denaturalisation powers in the 2000s were naive. The government of the day may have intended only judicious, sparing use of citizenship stripping. If so, the scope of those intentions were not reflected in the very wide powers the government conferred on itself and, importantly, on its successors. Subsequent governments have made ever more extensive use of the powers that were conferred on the Home Secretary.
In the process, two tiers of British citizenship have emerged. Those with no foreign parentage are relatively secure in their status because they would be rendered stateless if they lost their British citizenship, meaning the power cannot be exercised against them. But for those who have naturalised or have foreign parentage, British citizenship is now little more than a readily revocable form of immigration status.
What should be done?
Politicians rarely want to simply scrap the legislation their predecessors introduced. It opens them to the charge that they are a soft touch and that they have no alternative solution to the problem the legislation was intended to address. Generally, politicians prefer to substitute alternative legislation. This has the effect of scrapping the old laws but it offers a new way forward.
It would certainly be possible simply to amend the British Nationality Act 1981 once again in order to re-impose more robust legislative handcuffs and re-instate better procedural protections. But this seems an unlikely course of action for any government. Ministers will quickly find that civil servants place citizenship deprivation decisions in their inbox. When faced with such a decision and advised that failing to approve the decision places the British public at risk, no politician is going to refuse. One can understand why. How can they refuse? Parliament has conferred the power on them, surely they are obliged to do what the law allows them to do to protect the public? And it takes a very bold, principled person to give away powers once they are conferred.
A more realistic way forward would be to reset British citizenship law entirely. It is time for a British Citizenship Act. Starting over means consulting and offers an opportunity to adopt a principled and balanced set of powers.
That balancing exercise would need to involve finding a way to address the return of those like Shamima Begum who may have been involved in very poor conduct abroad. They should be held to account here in their own country. If criminal law prevents that it might be amended. New procedures or offences could be considered, including, if necessary, a reformed treason offence.
There are plenty of other reasons to consider a British Citizenship Act. For the first time in centuries, the United Kingdom fully controls its own constitutive membership. In the imperial era a very expansive — if sometimes illusory — concept of British subjecthood meant that millions of people around the globe all held a conceptually equal membership status. During membership of the European Union, the United Kingdom had very limited if any control over the entry and residence of European citizens.
Post-Brexit, it is time to think again about what it means to be a British citizen.
1) I was comparing the wording of the UK Oath of Allegiance which new citizens take with the equivalent US Oath. The US Oath is very specific. It requires citizens to “absolutely & entirely renounce and abjure all allegiance and fidelity to any foreign prince, potentate, state, or sovereignty.” I wonder if we should have wording more like that. It makes unambiguous that citizenship implies an overriding loyalty, which you are expected to uphold unconditionally.
2) I think stripping people like Shamima Begum of her UK citizenship is wrong. But the alternative, of allowing her back, has to involve at least the possibility of charging her with treason.
3) I notice that Keir Starmer intends to give 6 million non-UK citizens the right to vote in UK General Elections. I know this might sound incredibly cynical, but I suspect he thinks there is an electoral advantage for the Labour Party in doing this. It might also disincentivise people from bothering to take the citizenship test, since they will gain one of the main benefits of citizenship without taking it. Since we select juries based on the electoral roll, these non-citizens will also be available as jurors on any cases people such as Shamima Begum could be tried with if she is ever allowed to return to the UK. Sir Keir has not made clear whether these non-citizens could be conscripted in wartime.